Research Digest Beliefs, opinions, evidence and truth: guidance for information ethics in a business context

In “Epistemic Responsibility in Business: An Integrative Framework for an Epistemic Ethics”, published in the Journal of Business Ethics, ESCP Business School Professor Erwan Lamy proposes a theoretical framework and practical guidance for epistemic responsibility (related to truth) in a business context.

Why study this

In the age of fake news and ‘post-truth’, a crucial issue is the responsibility of businesspeople regarding the reliability of the information they spread. Indeed, intellectual dishonesty or even downright lies undermine the trust necessary for the economy to run smoothly. In some instances, a cavalier attitude towards information can even lead to disaster, like when leading US credit rating agencies not only severely underestimated the risk attached to financial products at the heart of the 2008 financial crisis, but also tried evading the liability attached to the exercise of their expertise. While it is unrealistic to expect absolute truth, or that errors never be made, it is desirable that businesses should do their best to control the value of the information they disseminate and be prepared to account for potential faults. Hence the notion of ‘epistemic responsibility’ explored in this paper.

Findings

  • The researcher proposes a theoretical framework to define epistemic values and faults, based on the sender-recipient model (a sender produces information which is conveyed to a recipient).
  • The epistemic value of a message is the assessment of the evidence or arguments produced to substantiate the information contained in the message.
  • The researcher identified the eight following epistemic values to define the notion of epistemic fault:
    • ‘Required’ epistemic value: an objective assessment (e.g. a bank may require certified accounts from a company before granting a loan).
    • ‘Expected’ epistemic value: the subjective needs of the recipient (an inexperienced banker may be willing to accept non-certified accounts from a loan applicant).
    • ‘Estimated’ epistemic value: the sender's perception of the epistemic needs of the recipient.
    • ‘Effective’ epistemic value: the objective assessment of the value of the evidence (e.g. the quality of the accountant's work in supplying loan application documents).
    • ‘Declared’ epistemic value: as declared by the sender (a credit rating agency assures that its ratings are quality work).
    • ‘Attributed epistemic value: perceived reliability of the information, from the sender's point of view.
    • ‘Received’ epistemic value: the value actually received (lower than the effective value if the recipient reads only the conclusion of a report but overlooks the supporting evidence).
    • ‘Final’ epistemic value: the value subjectively perceived by the recipient. 
  • When all eight of these values are aligned, they form the Norm of Epistemic Value Alignment (NEVA), the requirement that determines the conditions for the message to be asserted. 
  • An epistemic fault is committed by the sender or the recipient when deviations from NEVA occur and are epistemically undesirable, avoidable, and can be consciously perceived. 
  • Epistemic virtue is defined as a disposition to align different epistemic values, whereas epistemic vice is the disposition to misalign those values.

[Epistemic] requirements are obviously not the same for all individuals, nor for all businesses. When checking the security system of a nuclear plant, its security manager will require far more assurances regarding the capacity of the system to avoid any major failing than for the security system of, for example, a neighborhood laundromat, since the consequences of a failure in the former case are far greater than in the latter.

Key insight

The disposition to align epistemic values constitutes epistemic virtue, and the disposition to account for an alleged epistemic fault is constitutive of epistemic responsibility. 

Impact

The notion of epistemic responsibility would allow businesspeople to no longer fear being vilified when they have said something wrong, as long as they are epistemically virtuous - since epistemic responsibility is a question of being prepared to understand and correct epistemic faults. 

Final takeaway

“Being epistemically good does not necessarily mean telling the truth at all times, nor does it mean that epistemic faults will never be committed. It does mean cultivating epistemic virtues, by being driven by epistemic responsibility. This epistemic responsibility does not necessarily lead to an obligation of results (telling the truth, or not committing epistemic fault), but rather to an obligation of means (doing everything in one's power to avoid epistemic faults).”

AUTHOR


Erwan Lamy Erwan Lamy Associate Professor in the Information and Operations Management department at ESCP Business School

Campuses